jim.shamlin.com

19 - Fallacies

The word fallacy is broadly used to refer to a belief that is wrong (for whatever reason), but in terms of critical thinking it has a specific meaning: a fallacy is a mistake that violates the principles of correct reasoning. In that sense, a person can present factually accurate information, but still commit a fallacy.

In its strictest sense, fallacy is applied to the relationship between the premises and conclusion of a single argument - but because bad premises can lead to a bad conclusion, it is necessary to apply the notion of fallacy in a broader sense, to consider whether any given statement is fallacious.

Classifying Fallacies

There is no established and universal method of classifying fallacies -Aristotle in Greece and Xunzi in China classified them differently, and there are various ways of sorting them out. The author presents his own system, based on their nature:

The author has proposed this scheme because it is more intuitive. If you understand the reason a fallacy has occurred, you can then diagnose and identify it.

Fallacies of Inconsistency

A contradiction is a statement that negates itself - the statement "nothing is universal" is contradictory because the statement itself is meant to be taken as a universal. Not all contradictions are so obvious, and they often occur as a failure to clearly define premises, such that the conclusion seems "both right and wrong" because we haven't sorted out the conditions under which it is right or wrong.

A self-refuting claim is similar: if someone says "I do not speak any English" in English, then they do speak it (enough to say that sentence); or to say "I will not comment on my despicable wife" is to make a comment in the same sentence.

The single-sentence examples are a bit ludicrous and make it seem that contradiction would be rare - but it is a lot more common when two separate statements contradict one another. Not may people have examined their beliefs, and often hold contradictory ones that evidence themselves during the course of an argument.

Fallacies of Inappropriate Assumption

There are a number of fallacies that are based on an inappropriate assumption, or the presumption of truth that has not been established. Consider the following:

Circular Arguments

The statement that "we should study history because it is an important subject" provides no proof of its importance: we should study important subjects is one argument, history is an important subject is a second.

Many arguments involving religious premises become circular arguments because they assume something that an opponent is likely to deny. "It's true because it's in the Bible" carries no weight no someone who does not believe everything in the Bible to be true - and is based on the premise that it is.

False Dilemma

A false dilemma proposes a finite number of outcomes, assuming there to be no other possibility. The assertion "if you're not for us, you're against us" excludes the possibility that a person is not involved in the conflict at all.

The most common such dilemma is the question of whether something is "good or bad" without consideration of whether it may be neither good nor bad. There are many choices that are morally neutral under most circumstances.

Loaded Questions

In confrontational situations, people attempt to gain a point by trickery: "Did you wash your hands after killing your wife?" assumes that you killed your wife, and answering the question yes or no is taken as admission to the crime.

(EN: I'm familiar with the concept, but do not see the relevance to critical thinking. Looking to other sources, I really don't see it outside of political debate or courtroom drama - and as such I don't think it's a fallacy that might corrupt a person's critical thinking so much as an attempt to use wordplay to "prove" an argument that is known to be invalid.)

Fallacies of Irrelevance

Fallacies of irrelevance introduce information that has nothing to do with the subject of debate. The most common of these is the personal attack: "Only an idiot would believe that" does not address the argument at all. Race-baiting is a similar distraction - "only a racist would believe such a thing" is tossed out to distract from the argument and lead the other person to defend themselves on other grounds.

There are many related fallacies in which something is argued to be true based on an inappropriate appeal to something entirely irrelevant:

Appealing to tradition, association, or authority are not necessarily a fallacy - but they are not generally sufficient to prove a statement true without additional information.

Another source of an irrelevant statement is in assuming something unusual to be typical. "it must not be illegal to run a stop sign because I didn't get a ticket the last time I did so" assumes the traffic cops to be omnipresent (or even if there was one present, he wasn't paying attention).

Irrelevant responses are also common in argumentation when someone is attempting to cover up the truth with unrelated information. If a reporter asks if a police raid was authorized, the respondent may read a set of rules about when a raid is legally authorized without pointing out that the act in question did or did not meet those criteria. It is irrelevant because the reporter didn't ask what the rules were, but whether they were followed in a given instance.

A lot of advertising claims are likewise based on our susceptibility to irrelevant information. A product is called "fresh" but contains no fresh ingredients, a popular athlete is paid to endorse a product he does not use, a product that costs the same as its competitors claims to be a bargain, etc.

Fallacies of Insufficiency

A fallacy of insufficiency applies to an argument whose premises are too weak to support the conclusion, even though they are relevant.

Generalization is a common practice - using terms such as always/never or all/none when there is insufficient evidence. This is especially true when an unusual example is used to suggest something is true of the entire population (the fact that one graduate of a university won a Nobel prize is presented to suggest the quality of education). It is also true of statistics - the indication that 51% of people hold an opinion is meant to suggest it is true of "a majority", and then applied to all.

Consider the instances of medical misdiagnosis where the physician noticed few symptoms and jumped to a conclusion about their cause without doing a thorough examination of the patient. The same happens in argumentation with much greater frequency.

Insufficiency is also the key problem with weak analogies because they consider two items to be identical when they are only similar. What is true of cats is not true of horses simply because they are both domesticated quadrupeds - or to tap a hackneyed expression, what is true of apples is not true of oranges simply because they are both fruit.

A List of Fallacies

The author provides a list of common fallacies, which is far from comprehensive, but worth considering: